Translate

Wednesday, 3 June 2015


Historic U.S. Supreme Court Judgement

A historic decision was made in the U.S. Supreme Court on Monday 1st June.
It involved the case EEOC v. Abercrombie & Fitch.
It is historic not just for the majority decision or judgement but also for what is probably Justice Clarence Thomas' finest dissenting Opinion ever made as a Supreme Court Justice.

It is a case of enormous significance the reverberations of which will echo across America in the context of Civil Rights, Religious Freedom and the separation of Church and State.

I will admit that I have a personal interest in this judgement because many years ago I had knowledge of a similar situation along the lines of Abercrombie & Fitch which never reached the Courts.  The decision in the matter was not based on prejudice but on policy issues – but it likewise could (and perhaps was) perceived as based on personal prejudices. 
[Indeed for over two decades Ross Perot, the Founder of EDS, as a matter of company policy, would never hire any employee who wore a beard or moustache and it's Texas headquarters for new recruits was more akin to Boot Camp than induction training.]

This issue of headscarves also has a personal significance.   I grew up in a very traditional Christian community where women always covered themselves with a semi-veil or headscarf going into Church out of respect and tradition rather than because there were prohibitions against going uncovered.
For example, my mother and aunt would never think of going into a Church uncovered (without a headscarf) because such would be highly disrespectful.

The Case
centered around Samantha Elauf, a lady who wore a headscarf to her job interview with the firm Abercrombie & Fitch. They decided that while she ws qualified for the job, wearing a headscarf at work would be contrary to their 'appearance' policy.  On this basis they refused to employ her.
The EEOC took on her case.  The trial court ruled in favor of the EEOC-Elauf. Abercombie & Fitch appealed.  This decision was reversed by an appeals court who decided in favor of Abercrombie & Fitch.
By an 8-1 vote the U.S. Supreme Court have now reversed this decision.
What is even more important is the ruling by Justice Antonin Scalia who delivered the Opinion of The Court:
''Samantha Elauf is a practicing Muslim who, consistent with her understanding of her religion’s requirements,wears a headscarf.........
Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964 78 Stat. 253, as amended, prohibits two categories of employment practices. It is unlawful for an employer:
(1) to fail or refuse to hire or to discharge any individual, or otherwise to discriminate against any individual with respect to his compensation, terms, conditions, or privileges of employment, because of such individual’s race, color, religion, sex, or national origin;
or
(2)to limit, segregate, or classify his employees or applicants for employment in any way which would deprive or tend to deprive any individual of employment opportunities or otherwise adversely affect his status as an employee, because of such individual’s race, color, religion, sex, or national origin.”
These two proscriptions, often referred to as the “disparate treatment” (or “intentional discrimination”) provision and the “disparate impact” provision, are the only causes of action under Title VII. The word “religion” is defined to “includ[e] all aspects of religious observance and practice, as well as belief, unless an employer demonstrates that he is unable to reasonably accommodate to” areligious observance or practice without undue hardship in the conduct of the employer’s business.” §2000e(j).Abercrombie’s primary argument is that an applicant cannot show disparate treatment without first showing that an employer has “actual knowledge” of the applicant’s need for an accommodation. We disagree. Instead, an applicant need only show that his need for an accommodation was a motivating factor in the employer’s decision........''

2
''The disparate-treatment provision forbids employers to:
(1) fail . . . to hire” an applicant (2) “because of ” (3) “such individual’s . . . religion” (which includes his religious practice). Here, of course, Abercrombie (1) failed to hire Elauf. The parties concede that (if Elauf sincerely believes that her religion so requires) Elauf ’s wearing of a head scarf is (3) a “religious practice.” All that remains is whether she was not hired (2) “because of ” her religious practice.''

Concurring with the Judgement Justice Samuel Alito Jr.,added:
''In sum, the EEOC was required in this case to prove that Abercrombie rejected Elauf because of a practice that Abercrombie knew was religious. It is undisputed that Abercrombie rejected Elauf because she wore a headscarf, and there is ample evidence in the summary judgment record to prove that Abercrombie knew that Elauf is a Muslim and that she wore the scarf for a religious reason. The Tenth Circuit therefore erred in ordering the entry of summary judgment for Abercrombie. On remand, the Tenth Circuit can consider whether there is sufficient evidence to support summary judgment in favor of the EEOC on the question of Abercrombie’s knowledge. The Tenth Circuit will also be required to address Abercrombie’s claim that it could not have accommodated Elauf ’s wearing the headscarf on the job without undue hardship.''

The Dissenting Voice (concurring in part and dissenting in other parts) In This Case Was That Of Justice Clarence Thomas:
''JUSTICE THOMAS, concurring in part and dissenting in part.''
''I agree with the Court that there are two—and only two—causes of action under Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964 as understood by our precedents: a disparate treatment (or intentional-discrimination) claim and a disparate-impact claim. Ante,at 3. Our agreement ends there. Unlike the majority, I adhere to what I had thought before today was an undisputed proposition: Mere application of a neutral policy cannot constitute “intentional discrimination.” Because the Equal Employment Opportunity Commission (EEOC) can prevail here only if Abercrombie engaged in intentional discrimination, and because Abercrombie’s application of its neutral Look Policy does not meet that description, I would affirm the judgment of the Tenth Circuit.''
I
''This case turns on whether Abercrombie’s conduct constituted “intentional discrimination” within the mean ing of 42 U. S. C. §1981a(a)(1). That provision allows a Title VII plaintiff to “recover compensatory and punitive damages” only against an employer “who engaged in unlawful intentional discrimination (not an employment practice that is unlawful because of its disparate impact).” The damages award EEOC obtained against Abercrombie is thus proper only if that company engaged in “intentional discrimination”—as opposed to “an employment practice that is unlawful because of its disparate impact”—within the meaning of §1981a(a)(1).
The terms “intentional discrimination” and “disparate impact” have settled meanings in federal employment discrimination law. “[I]ntentional discrimination . . .
occur[s] where an employer has treated a particular person less favorably than others because of a protected trait.” Ricci v.DeStefano, 557 U. S. 557, 577 (2009) (internal quotation marks and alteration omitted). [D]isparate-impact claims,” by contrast, “involve employment practices that are facially neutral in their treatment of different groups but that in fact fall more harshly on one group than another and cannot be justified by business necessity.” Raytheon Co.v.Hernandez , 540 U. S. 44, 52 (2003) (internal quotation marks omitted). Conceived by this Court in Griggs v. Duke Power Co., 401 U. S. 424 (1971), this “theory of discrimination” provides that “a facially neutral employment practice may bedeemed illegally discriminatory without evidence of the employer’s subjective intent to discriminate that is required in a disparate-treatment case,” Raytheon, supra,at 52–53 (internal quotation marks and alteration omitted).
I would hold that Abercrombie’s conduct did not constitute “intentional discriminatio
n.” Abercrombie refused to create an exception to its neutral Look Policy for Samantha Elauf ’s religious practice of wearing a headscarf. Ante,at 2. In doing so, it did not treat religious practices less favorably than similar secular practices, but instead remained neutral with regard to religious practices. To be sure, the effects of Abercrombie’s neutral Look Policy, absent an accommodation, fall more harshly on those who wear headscarves as an aspect of their faith. But that is a classic case of an alleged disparate impact. It is not what we have previously understood to be a case of disparate treatment because Elauf received the same treatment from Abercrombie as any other applicant who appeared unable to comply with the company’s Look Policy. See ibid. ; App. 134, 144. Because I cannot classify Abercrombie’s conduct as “intentional discrimination,” I would affirm. ''
II
A
''Resisting this straightforward application of §1981a, the majority expands the meaning of “intentional discrimination” to include a refusal to give a religious applicantfavored treatment.” Ante,at 6–7. But contrary to the majority’s assumption, this novel theory of discrimination is not commanded by the relevant statutory text. Title VII makes it illegal for an employer “to fail or refuse to hire . . . any individual . . . because of such individual’s . . . religion.” §2000e–2(a)(1). And as used in Title VII, “[t]he term ‘religion’ includes all aspects of religious observance and practice, as well as belief, unless an employer demonstrates that he is unable to reasonably accommodate to an employee’s or prospective employee’s religious observance or practice without undue hardship on the conduct of the employer’s business.” §2000e(j). With this gloss on the definition of “religion” in §2000e 2(a)(1), the majority concludes that an employer may violate Title VII if he “refuse[s] to hire . . . any individual . . . because of such individual’s . . . religious . . . practice” (unless he has an “undue hardship” defense). See ante,at 3–4. But inserting the statutory definition of religion into §2000e–2(a) does not answer the question whether Abercrombie’s refusal to hire Elauf was “because of her religious practice.” At first glance, the phrase “because of such individual’s religious practice” could mean one of two things. Under one reading, it could prohibit taking an action because of the religious nature of an employee’s particular practice. Under the alternative reading, it could prohibit taking an action because of an employee’s practice that happens to be religious.''
''The distinction is perhaps best understood by example. Suppose an employer with a neutral grooming policy forbidding facial hair refuses to hire a Muslim who wears a beard for religious reasons. Assuming the employer applied the neutral grooming policy to all applicants, the motivation behind the refusal to hire the Muslim applicant would not be the religious nature of his beard, but its existence. Under the first reading, then, the Muslim applicant would lack an intentional-discrimination claim, as he was not refused employment “because of ” the religious nature of his practice. But under the second reading, he would have such a claim, as he was refused employment “because of ” a practice that happens to be religious in nature. ''
''One problem with the second, more expansive reading is that it would punish employers who have no discriminatory motive. If the phrase “because of such individual’s religious practice” sweeps in any case in which an employer takes an adverse action because of a practice that happens to be religious in nature, an employer who had no idea that a particular practice was religious would be penalized. That strict-liability vi ew is plainly at odds with the concept of intentional discrimination. Cf.Raytheon, supra,at 54, n. 7 (“If [the employer] were truly unaware that such a disability existed, it would be impossible for her hiring decision to have been based, even in part, on[the applicant’s] disability. And, if no part of the hiring decision turned on [the applicant’s] status as disabled, he cannot, ipso facto, have been subject to disparate treatment”). Surprisingly, the majority leaves the door open to this strict-liability theory, reserving the question whether an employer who does not even “suspec[t] that the practice in question is a religious practice” can nonetheless be punished for intentional discrimination. ''
Ante,at 6, n. 3. ''For purposes of today’s decision, however, the majority opts for a compromise, albeit one that lacks a foothold in the text and fares no better under our precedents. The majority construes §2000e–2(a)(1) to punish employers
who refuse to accommodate applicants under neutral policies when they act “with the motive of avoiding accommodation.”
Ante, at 5. ''But an employer who is aware that strictly applying a neutral policy will have an adverse effect on a religious group, and applies the policy anyway,
is not engaged in intentional discrimination, at least as that term has traditionally been understood. As the Court explained many decades ago, “ ‘Discriminatory purpose’i.e., the purpose necessary for a claim of intentional discrimination—demands “more than . . . awareness of consequences. It implies that the decisionmaker . . . selected or reaffirmed a particular course of action at least in part because of,’ not merely ‘in spite of,’ its adverse effects upon an identifiable group.” ''Personnel Administrator of Mass. v.Feeney , 442 U. S. 256, 279 (1979) (internal citation and footnote omitted). I do not dispute that a refusal to accommodate can, in some circumstances, constitute intentional discrimination. If an employer declines to accommodate a particular religious practice, yet accommodates a similar secular (or other denominational) practice, then that may be proof that he has “treated a particular person less favorably than others because of [a religious practice].” Ricci , 557 U. S., at 577 (internal quotation marks and alteration omitted); see also, e.g., Dixon v. Hallmark Cos., 627 F. 3d 849, 853 (CA11 2010) (addressing a policy forbidding display of “religious items” in management offices). But merely refusing to create an exception to a neutral policy for a religious practice canno t be described as treating a particular applicant “less favorably than others.” The majority itself appears to recognize that its construction requires something more than equal treatment. See ante, at 6–7 (“Title VII does not demand mere neutrality with regard to religious practices,” but instead “gives them favored treatment”). But equal treatment is not disparate treatment, and that basic principle should have disposed of this case. ''…......................''The Court today rightly puts to rest the notion that Title VII creates a freestanding religious-accommodation claim, ante,at 3, but creates in its stead an entirely new form of liability: the disparate-treat ment-based-on-equal-treatment claim. Because I do not think that Congress’ 1972 redefinition of “religion” also redefined “intentional discrimination,” I would affirm the judgment of the Tenth Circuit. I respectfully dissent from the portions of the majority’s decision that take the contrary view. ''


                                               [Judgement ends]
  
References:
                                                         

   
 The above picture/print is either in The Holy Land, Persia, Ottoman Syria, Yemen or other Persian Gulf area circa 1896-1902
                                          ©Patrick Emek, 2015


















Blog Archive